Ellickson, Order Without Law (1991)
This book explains how Robert Ellickson changed his mind about the role of law in providing order in society. He'd started from a premise for which Ronald Coase is famous: that people start where the legal system places them and negotiate from there to mutually useful outcomes. Coase presented a now famous theory that if transaction costs were zero, a change in the legal rules would have no effect because people would just negotiate to the allocation of resources that existed before the law was changed.
On the ground in Shasta County, California, Ellickson studied the ways that real-life ranchers resolved disputes over wandering cattle on land that was "open range," where branded cattle roamed free and unfenced until rounded up for market. Sometimes they ate up a neighbor's hay, broke his fences, or blocked roads, sometimes triggering auto accidents. Most of these disputes were resolved without resort to law, and often were resolved in a way contrary to the legal rules.
His theory, presented and supported in his book, is that people would often resolve disputes by applying community norms, without paying any attention to the legal rules that apply to those disputes. And that this occurs even though they have contrary interests and do not have alturistic motives. Their methods and results were often actually contrary to what the legal rules called for, and the community often actively resisted and discouraged those who "went to law" to resolve certain disputes.
Order Often Arises Spontaneously
What Ellickson found surprised him: "Order often arises spontaneously. Although many other writers have recognized this point, it remains counterintuitive and cannot be repeated too often. * * * According to [Thomas] Hobbes, without a Leviathan (government) to issue and enforce commands, all would be endless strife. The Shasta County evidence shows that Hobbes was much too quick to equate anarchy with chaos. Many entitlements, especially workaday entitlements, can arise spontaneously. People may supplement, and indeed preempt, the state's rules with rules of their own." Ellickson, p. 4.
Ellickson's analysis divided the rules that emerge in complex societies into five overlapping categories (and their origins) : personal ethics (self-discipline), contracts (agreement), norms (social effects), organization rules (non-governments), and law (government). Each of these categories has its own type of sanction, either positive or negative: self-sanctions, personal self-help, vicarious self-help, organization enforcement and state enforcement.
What Ellickson found in Shasta County was that when residents resolved their disputes among themselves, they typically did so in total ignorance of their legal rights, and applied societal norms that effectively supplanted legal rights and obligations. He found that self-help enforcement was common, even escalating to violence against offending cattle if the owner did not respond to less stringent self-help sanctions. He also found that they rarely used attorneys to resolve disputes. Under these circumstances, discernable norms emerged that were well known and followed by Shasta County residents.
Theories of Close-Knit Groups
Ellickson presented his own theory based upon the actual behavior observed in his and others' studies of the emergence of norms among groups:
"Members of a close-knit group develop and maintain norms whose content serves to maximize the aggregate welfare that members obtain in their workaday affairs with one another." Stated another way, "the hypothesis predicts that members of tight social groups will informally encourage each other to engage in cooperative behavior." Ellickson, p. 167.
When he refers to "maximizing welfare" he means getting to the highest possible group aggregate of all outcomes that people value, not just commodities but also intangbles "such as parenthood, leisure, good health, high social status, and close personal relationships." Id. p. 170.
By "workaday affairs" he does not include two kinds of foundational rules: the ground rules of property ownership and exchange (e.g., no deliberate theft or vandalism, no murder) and purely distributive norms like that encouraging charity.
By "close-knit" he means a group in which "informal power is broadly distributed among group members and the information pertinent to informal control circulates easily among them." Id. p. 178. A close-knit group is one in which the members can expect to interact in the future, they know each other's history and everyone will "have their day" when the power tables will be turned.
The Shadow of the Future
Other scholars of game theory, notably Axelrod, have documented the importance of this "shadow of the future:" each member's knowledge that there will come a time when the other member(s) will have the opportunity to make "get even" for past behavior (good or bad). The knowledge of these unavoidable future encounters has a distinct effect in encouraging cooperation, because those that don't cooperate know that they are likely to be punished by one or more of their peers in the future. This situation is summed up in the common caution: "remember, I have to work with these people every day."
But that knowledge alone is not enough to trigger the emergence of cooperative behavior. The other essential ingredient is some information about the past and the present. Close-knit groups with many links help members maintain a gossip network through which truthful reports move, sharing how certain members behaved in certain circumstances in the past.
Close-knittedness does not require a group to have exclusive claim on one member; one can simultaneously be a member of several close-knit groups (e.g. a work group, a residence group and a political group). Also, even a large group can be close-knit, although small groups are more likely to have higher quality of gossip, reciprocity of power and ease of enforcement.
In his book Ellickson went on to explore how his theory seemed to explain various social norms that developed among various groups that operated essentially outside of the reach of formal law, such as those among cattlemen in Shasta County and those among 18th century whalers.
He went on for several chapters discussing the various types of norms and the various ways in which group members can exert positive sanctions (rewards) and negative sanctions (punishments) on members whose behavior exceeded or fell below group norms.
Law is Expensive, and Community Norms More Expeditious
Ellickson found that people may ignore "law" because they realize that resort to formal legal processes is expensive, especially for small-stakes matters, and "going to law" often makes social relationships worse. Another reason is that they have more expeditious means to obtain order, when they are in close-knit groups that can govern minor problems using informal norms enforced by means such as truthful negative gossip and mild physical reprisals. When those conditions apply, "informal social controls are likely to supplant law." Id. p. 282.
Formal law does have a role to play, in enabling such informal controls. Writes Ellickson: "To achieve order without law, people must have continuing relationships, reliable information about past behavior, and effective countervailing power. * * * Legal rules can influence all these attributes of social structure and thereby promote -- or impede -- informal cooperation." Id. p. 284.
As an example, Ellickson points to land laws; those that encourage subdivision of land among multiple owners reinforces their realization that they will be long-term neighbors, and divides the interest in keeping things up, increasing among them the likelihood of cooperation. The ability to sell land to another also enhances cooperation by giving an owner an interest in maintaining the value of the property even after she has sold and left. Law can also encourage symmetries of power and discourage assymetric situations, in which one or a few parties have disproportionate power over others, leaving an imbalance that allows those "on the bottom" little opportunity to pay back uncooperative behavior.
Requests for Comment:
Have you read Ellickson's book or about these theories elsewhere?
Do they make sense to you, or seem to be bogus?
If there is something to them, in what ways do you see these theories possibly applied in SL?
Think of some groups or communities in SL. Are those that seem to be self-organized the ones that are more "close-knit" as Ellickson describes them?
If Ellickson is right, what characteristics would one look for or try to install in a SL community or group if one wanted to increase informal enforcement of useful societal norms, such as land use zoning, or avoidance of certain conducts?
What does Ellickson's theory say to you about approaches to setting up or joining new groups or land parcels in SL?